Skip to main content

The Being at the Center: The Human Dilemma as the Core of Philosophical Anthropology

            Paul Ricoeur noticed that the various body of knowledge, in their take on the human being, end up being insufficient in grasping humanity at its core. These “sciences” end up reducing the human being to static episodes that can be instrumentalized; thus, these analyses diminish the intricacy of a human being’s existence. Ricoeur begs the question “who is this being for whom being is in question?”[1]

               Ricoeur establishes that a human being is in between the infinite and finite poles of which this theme in describing humans is evident in Plato, Pascal, and Kierkegaard. Moreover, since humanity is situated in between the poles, he or she is caught between a seeming conflict of goals. And in this caught-in-the-middle situation lies humanity’s fallibility (tendency to err) which constitutes his or her fragility. Thus, this situation calls for what Ricoeur means on having a philosophical anthropology. Philosophical in the sense that it does not anchor its analysis on the inevitability of the other sciences to reduce humans to functional or operative descriptions. Furthermore, philosophical anthropology tackles on the human being’s predicament as finitude-infinitude-intermediary.

               Philosophical anthropology takes its roots in the Pathos or Wretchedness (former is referring to Plato while the latter to Pascal), and this root is born from the finitude-infinitude-intermediary situation of humanity. More so, the stress on the intermediary is crucial because it is that which stands in between the poles wherein this middle can pass through either to or fro to the corruptible and incorruptible or finite and the infinite. Ricoeur notes that even Plato, for a lack of a better term, analogizes in his description of the intermediary as the “city” (as the center) and even mythologizes on the origin such as the “fall” of the soul. In these descriptions or attempt to appropriately linguistically express the intermediary, philosophical anthropology takes place.

               Moreover, Ricoeur continues with the efforts of philosophical anthropology through Pascal. Pascal’s description of the intermediary takes on a spatial form of reference to that being in between the very large and the very small wherein such situation he dubs as wretchedness. This situation makes humans caught in between infinites that shows how limited one is in grasping the first principles and can only make do what is apparent. To Pascal, “nothing can affix the finite between the two infinites that both enclose and escape it.”[2] Yet, this expression of the intermediary fails to suffice as an accurate description of the human situation.

               Ricoeur then turns to Kierkegaard as the Danish's description speaks closely of what the intermediary is. Thus, Ricoeur lifted a statement from Kiekegaard’s Sickness Unto Death saying that humans or this intermediary is “a relation that relates itself (freedom) and in relating itself to itself relates itself to another.”[3] This description offers more fluidity of the human situation as compared to Plato and Pascal which simply describes the human situation as being caught in the middle. However, Kierkegaard’s statement puts life to the intermediary as something that is constantly in relation to something. Yet, Ricoeur sees Kierkegaard’s statement as rhetorical.

               In the search for the appropriate notion of the intermediary that evades rather a mythological or analogical referencing, Ricoeur turns to Kant’s transcendental imagination as a “better” alternative to that of previous three thinkers. Ricoeur posed the question on “why is this resistance of mythos to logos?”[4] to show that even from the efforts of the philosophers, achieving a logos into philosophical anthropology is a little bit farfetched.

               In Kant, the transcendental imagination is where the ability to situate oneself in the present and projects beyond oneself occurs. This intermediary is considered as the “fault line” that through reflection one can be then situated in between sensibility and understanding. More so, the peculiar phenomenon of this recognition of the transcendental intermediary among others is a presumption through respect. Respect is wherein one sees in the other as in this culminative situation of poles and then later on ascribes oneself through the object, in turn, respecting oneself. Also, this transcendental imagination stands above feeling and thinking, and it is a synthesis of the two. This synthesis is evident in the object wherein in reflection, the intermediary can be deduced. Thus, the human being, even amidst the dichotomy of being and nothing or the finite and the infinite, acts as an intermediary of both. This description then points to consciousness as in between wherein this consciousness of the self, objects, and others is evidence enough to convey the middle, the intermediary, or the third term facilitating all of these.[5]

               After establishing through descriptions what an intermediary is that constitutes the interest of philosophical anthropology, Ricoeur “brings down” the intermediary to the practical wherein the being in the middle is always in a situation, and this time, a concrete one. Thus, Ricoeur sparks the antinomy of character and happiness in the level of praxis.

               For Ricoeur, “character is the generalization of the notion of perspective”[6] and that “perspective is the human point of view on things as things.”[7] Using the previous description of the poles from the previous analysis, character here is in the finite. Finite as it is, then it is limited to perspectives that which it can grasp for the moment. Also, a perspective on something assumes an intentionality towards that something wherein such intentionality later on turns into desire especially, finite as a human being is, humanity searches for what is lacking. Desire has its temporality embedded in humanity’s finitude, yet the end of it all consummates in an infinitude i.e., happiness. Thus, Ricoeur says that “character is the perspectival orientation of our total field of motivation. Happiness is the end toward which all my motivation is oriented.”[8]

               The polarity of character and happiness constitutes the human being i.e., acting in the present and the immediate while pursuing the end and the infinite. Thus, this polarity is what makes humans fragile. And this makes the quest to act accordingly to the polarity which is to unite the polarities is a task due to the constant tensions between character and happiness. Moreover, this fragility and the task in uniting polarities presupposes that within the experience of such, human beings feel. Feeling is an occurrence as an intermediary between life and thoughts which enacts the intentionality towards something in an ever more intimate fashion.

               To Ricoeur, feeling needs to have a place as this is the most intimate point within a person. Feeling is this closeness with an experience, or an object as contrasted to objectification which there is a sense of distance or detachment. And “for a philosophical anthropology, knowing and feeling (objectivizing and internalizing) go together.”[9] Since feeling is this occurrence between bios and logos, in feeling, then comes Pathos. This Pathos is also the thumos wherein the instance of fragility is shown. The thumos, in its lack or situatedness in the middle, has passions to compensate for the lack. And Ricoeur borrows from Kant wherein the thumos can be linguistically pointed out into the three passions namely a) having, b) power, and c) worth. All of these three passions further describe or demythologizes the rather mystic linguistic ascription of the intermediary as the thumos. So, in the act of fulfilling these passions, human fragility takes into play. Humans desire for all three with the goal as well to achieve happiness.

IMPLICATIONS OF HUMAN FRAGILITY TO THE SOCIAL AND POLITICAL SPHERE

               This analysis of Paul Ricoeur on the Antinomy of Human Reality and the Problem of a Philosophical Anthropology shows the tension that an individual experiences as he or she exist. In pointing out human fragility as the quest in fulfilling the passions and that the human situation is oscillating to and fro in the poles of finitude and infinitude or character (perspectival) and happiness (infinite), Ricoeur shows the fundamental Pathos one is immersed into. This experience of the Pathos will lead to scenarios that will be critical once such is elevated into the social sphere i.e., when man relates with others. Although the Pathos can be smoothly seen as a fact of existence that one has to encounter with, the implications of such when different Pathos or intermediaries meet creates further tension.

               Greater problems will arise when different individuals, with presumed freedoms, in the state of acting towards the fulfillment of desires, meet. This meet or encounter with the other creates another struggle within human fragility as the fulfillment of desires will encounter hurdles. However, mutuality and respect can easily patch things up; yet the fragility remains and the problem of steering away from what is agreed upon in mutuality is immanent due to the fragility itself.

               In Ricoeur’s borrowing of Kant’s three passions (to appropriately “linguistify” Plato’s thumos), having, power, and worth all spell a big dilemma in the current social and political sphere. Once power is held by a person, then it spells a huge struggle for the others in want of that passion as well. Issues as such are tackled in Ricoeur’s other works. However, it is in this pinning down of philosophical anthropology that gave us a possible picture of what will be the problems once individuals are immersed in society.

               The big question lies in how can a community best cope up with its individual fragilities? Although institutions are present to smoothen out the possible anarchy when freedoms are all left at play without a greater intermediary, can humanity achieve a commonality when it comes to their fragility especially that in the fulfillment of the infinite (happiness) will encounter differences in the various modes available to humanity (perspectival happiness or pleasure). Will institutions suffice to be the greater intermediary for all individuals who are mediating their own polarities in their existence?

              

 



[1] Paul Ricoeur, Philosophical Anthropology: Writings and Lectures, Volume 3, ed. John Michel & Jerome Poree, trans. David Pellauer (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2016) 1.

[2] Ibid., 5

[3] Ibid., 5

[4] Ibid., 6

[5] Ibid., 10

[6] Ibid., 11

[7] Ibid., 11 

[8] Ibid., 13

            [9] Ibid., 15

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Article Review on Elinita Garcia's "Gabriel Marcel: Primary and Secondary Reflection"

Summary:             Gabriel Marcel is a known French existentialist. His co-Frenchman, Jean-Paul Sartre, distinguished existentialism into two which were coined as  atheistic  and  theistic  (Christian) wherein Sartre did mention Marcel as part of the latter in lecture on Existentialism a Humanism . Marcel is a Christian existentialist because he included the divine even amidst the infamous perception of existentialism as godless. Moreover, he is also known for his non-systematic philosophy where he pointed out that the philosophical discipline starts from where one is (referring to the particularity of the situation); therefore, it is not from metaphysical assumptions or already laid down theories.             Marcel’s thoughts talk about the importance and the necessity of reflection wherein he divides it into two as a) primary reflection and b) secondary reflection. Reflection for Marcel is “nothing other than attention, i.e. directed towards this sort of small break

Fin?

  Last 2012, there were hearts on fire that both had their first shared flame in an unlikely place. I was thirsty for love coming from being dormant while she was searching for a redemption from a series of broken hearts. Both struggled to find their place. Both trying to live their lives free from the hideous chains of a dark home. I must admit that I fell for her beauty and add to that, her care. As we both clasped our hands, it was a committed long shot to have the perfect rest for our hearts. It was a bit strange to have an affair under the noses of all that is forbidden both profession and a line of faith. Nothing was wrong as long both were in the ecstasy of love – no malice, no foul play, no trespassing of wills. That moment was a perfect episode in a romantic film – one where young love sprang amidst treacherous circumstances. We lived through the happiness of newfound belongingness and the battle of keeping that alive. 4 years before the wedlock were filled with ups and do

Bertrand Russell and the Sense of Sin

Introduction             Ethics is this study of what is good and what is bad and throughout the course of history it had also its shares of disputes and animosities. But beneath all of it is that ethics is a means in order to arrive at happiness or the good life. Because we have to act correspondingly or in a certain manner wherein we can get to attain harmony within ourselves especially regarding to our conscience or in harmony with others in order to keep relationships or ultimately to preserve one’s self or to attain such security whether externally and that is in relation with others or internally or personal satisfaction. Our actions are guided by principles of which we take actions correspondingly but the question lies what then are these principles and sometimes we go back to our way of understanding or our metaphysical assumptions wherein we garner from these in order to make way into how we conduct ourselves in our actions. In this paper then, I will explicate Bertrand