Skip to main content

On Ricoeur's State and Violence

 ON THE LIMITS OF VIOLENCE AND WHERE THE STATE WILL END

               Humans are undeniably situated in institutions such as a state which is a product of human interaction and the fulfillment of freedoms in individuals. Amidst this fulfillment of freedoms between individuals, the state has a peculiar role at its disposal – enactment of violence. Ricoeur noticed this peculiarity because states have always enacted in someway that uses violence to assert itself with legitimacy. Thus, Ricoeur asks: “What is the minimum violence instituted by the state?”[1]

               The legitimacy of violence stemming from the state constitutes its power and authority. Power in the sense that it can do something i.e., enactment of violence per se. More so, this enactment of violence compliments its authority, as without the minimal ability to be violent, the state cannot put to teeth its commanding capability. The minimal and yet acceptable violence the state can ever do is that which is penal by nature.

               Since the state can enact violence as its mandate with legitimacy, this causes a problem as states are not perfect and errors can occur being the arbiter and implementer of moral consciousness.[2] As the implementer and arbiter of moral consciousness, Ricoeur highlights the two ethics wherein the state can find itself in a problematic situation other than causing errors in judgements. The state must act as a magistrate, thus implement violence, and at the same time, the Christian practical ideal i.e., the ethic of love (love thy neighbor which offers reconciliation and non-resistance). The duality is present in the Pauline Epistles wherein Paul preaches about love as how it was delivered in the Sermon on the Mount while at the same time encouraging the people (to whom he was preaching of which his message is ripe for the cause of those who do not take Roman authority) not to take an anarchistic stance (coming from the newly acquired social identity as “Christians” in a Roman society) out from conscience and to be submissive to lawful authorities.[3]

               Paul recognized the Roman authority (or any specific authority within the vastness of the Roman Empire) during his time, and that is evidence of him recognizing the authority of the state as with it, its capacity to enact violence which he subtly warns people by looking into their conscience. Again, the limit of this violence should be penal in nature (no recourse to murder) that is anchored on justice. And as Ricoeur further investigates he said: “But it is precisely this established violence, this violence of justice which constitutes a problem.”[4] As any form of violence negates the ethic of love as violence is simply an evil given as compensation to the individual who does evil.

               The love that was preached in the Sermon on the Mount is in apparent contradiction with the magistrate. The magistrate has a commanding appeal to it and tenderness is not part of its manner in imposing its authority. And from a subject’s perspective, “the state is not my brother and requires submission.”[5] This is the undeniable dilemma of the state, and in its enactment of violence to impose itself, it can never cure evil. It maintains order to preserve the people institutionalizing it, but never can it eradicate evil altogether.[6]

               The continuation and preservation of humanity through the state is not stable as violence continually reverberates due to violence committed of humans against their fellow humans together with the state in its imposition of power and authority. “[Thus], order is not something tranquil and absolutely stable; order vibrates; order is a power.”[7] Up until this point, this speaks of the state managing itself. The brewing problem is on the state’s survival in the face of other states. Ricoeur recalls Machiavelli for this, as an undeniable reality between warring states needs attention. States go to war against other states for it to continue their continued existence. Machiavelli enticed war as a means for survival and assertion of existence of which poses a bigger problem. The problem lies in the act of war itself that is sacrificing individuals for the perpetuation of the state which violates already the ethic of love and prohibition of murder as the limit to its violence. Thus, a new tension lies among individuals caught in the war, (ethics of distress) and that is to continue his or her obedience or become what Ricoeur calls a “conscientious objector.”

               Being a conscientious objector puts a risk for the one objecting and the state he or she objected, as the state can enact violence to the apparent treason one is doing, or the objector will object through violence as the only means to equate its capacity to “correct” the state in turn, threatening the state. In despising war as an instrument of the state to perpetuate itself in the face of other states,  those who object create the possibilities for the inevitability of violence as a means to go against such mandate. This violence against the state within its subjects is what we call a revolution, and such poses another dilemma as Ricoeur says:

“For I cannot will, with a positive and deliberate volition, the death of my state without at the same time willing, through the conjunction of these major cataclysms, war and revolution, the violent institution of a new state, of a new sovereignty, a new power which win turn will summon my armed and murderous disobedience.”[8]

               In the desire to quell the murderous state, one is poised towards the inevitability of using murder as well first, to contradict the mandate, and second, to attempt to establish another order, perhaps, a new state. This situation is the magnification of the ethics of distress into another plane. Thus, can violence be stopped? Can people “correct” the state in its murderous path without resorting to the same violence that it shows? And here Ricoeur then concludes that:

“The end of this duality (tension between the ethic of love and the magisterium) would be the total reconciliation of man with man. But this would also be the end of the state, because this will be the end of history.”[9]

FORESIGHT ONTO THE END OF HISTORY

               Ricoeur’s State and Violence made implications that a state exists due to its enactment of violence, and the bare minimum and acceptable form of it is through punishments (penal and corrective by nature). Since a state cannot do without violence during its imposition of authority and a reflection of its power, a state cannot exist without its violence as well. However, Ricoeur shows his subtle opposition of the states using war (another form of violence) to further its existence by describing what a conscientious objector does. Yet, even war, a violent act, has its bottom line goal of the continued existence of the state as its end goal even at the expense of the subjects who are caught in the ethic of distress.

               Would it be safe to say that to Rcicoeur, a state exists side by side with its violence? And would it be fair also to consider the possibility that the absence of violence in any instance whatsoever means there is no reason anymore that a state exists; thus, the end of violence is also the end of the state? Even without alluding to Marx’s Historical Materialism, such hints on communism as this final stage of human history where there are no more contradictions, and there is a classless society. (I am referring to communism as how it was postulated when society transcends from the socialistic stage.) Moreover, this spells of what Vladimir Lenin take of Engel’s Anti-Duhring in State and Revolution as the “withering of the state.”

               The point where the state completely withers, shows a radical return to what people are prior to Ricoeur’s Third Person (Institutions) in his lecture The Problem with the Foundation of Moral Philosophy. A return which means that the there is the mutual understanding between people in the exercise of their freedoms minus the institution and along with it, a violence imposed to mediate and fulfill the freedoms within the institution. This description of humanity without institutions and in mutual understanding of each other for me, is ahistorical as to ascribe such as an origin or that which is prior to the state is not the same simply describing it as an occurrence along and within the fact that there is a state.

               Mutual understanding (in a perfect sense) is the radical fulfillment of the ethics of love of which Ricoeur labels as a practical ideal, but still carries with the ideal nature of such event. Ideal in the sense that the total fulfillment of such cannot be made manifest in human history. Yet this is also the dream of the Judeo-Christian tradition, and that is when the Kingdom of God has finally realized itself within human history. (A utopia yet still bears a magistrate, God as King which also begs the questions, what use of such magistrate when all is in perfection, thus, no errors and no reason for such magistrate to enact penal violence.) So, is human history what it is as it is also the occurrence of violence from both the individual and the state?

               This cycle of violence, especially when the state uses war as an instrument and when the people object to such violently, truly brings about the movement of history. Kingdoms and empires rise and fall via its enactment of violence within itself and externally, and as well as those who object violently to the regimes. History is marked with revolutions and long-standing rule of societies, and the total fulfillment of the ethics of love will be the end of it all. The cure to all evils ends the necessity of the state’s existence.



[1] Paul Ricoeur, History and Truth, trans. By Charles A. Kelbley (Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1965) 234.

[2] Ibid., 235

[3] Ibid., 236

[4] Ibid., 237

[5] Ibid., 237

[6] Ibid., 238 – 239

[7] Ibid., 240

[8] Ibid., 245

[9] Ibid., 246

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Article Review on Elinita Garcia's "Gabriel Marcel: Primary and Secondary Reflection"

Summary:             Gabriel Marcel is a known French existentialist. His co-Frenchman, Jean-Paul Sartre, distinguished existentialism into two which were coined as  atheistic  and  theistic  (Christian) wherein Sartre did mention Marcel as part of the latter in lecture on Existentialism a Humanism . Marcel is a Christian existentialist because he included the divine even amidst the infamous perception of existentialism as godless. Moreover, he is also known for his non-systematic philosophy where he pointed out that the philosophical discipline starts from where one is (referring to the particularity of the situation); therefore, it is not from metaphysical assumptions or already laid down theories.             Marcel’s thoughts talk about the importance and the necessity of reflection wherein he divides it into two as a) primary reflection and b) secondary reflection. Reflection for Marcel is “nothing other than attention, i.e. directed towards this sort of small break

Fin?

  Last 2012, there were hearts on fire that both had their first shared flame in an unlikely place. I was thirsty for love coming from being dormant while she was searching for a redemption from a series of broken hearts. Both struggled to find their place. Both trying to live their lives free from the hideous chains of a dark home. I must admit that I fell for her beauty and add to that, her care. As we both clasped our hands, it was a committed long shot to have the perfect rest for our hearts. It was a bit strange to have an affair under the noses of all that is forbidden both profession and a line of faith. Nothing was wrong as long both were in the ecstasy of love – no malice, no foul play, no trespassing of wills. That moment was a perfect episode in a romantic film – one where young love sprang amidst treacherous circumstances. We lived through the happiness of newfound belongingness and the battle of keeping that alive. 4 years before the wedlock were filled with ups and do

Bertrand Russell and the Sense of Sin

Introduction             Ethics is this study of what is good and what is bad and throughout the course of history it had also its shares of disputes and animosities. But beneath all of it is that ethics is a means in order to arrive at happiness or the good life. Because we have to act correspondingly or in a certain manner wherein we can get to attain harmony within ourselves especially regarding to our conscience or in harmony with others in order to keep relationships or ultimately to preserve one’s self or to attain such security whether externally and that is in relation with others or internally or personal satisfaction. Our actions are guided by principles of which we take actions correspondingly but the question lies what then are these principles and sometimes we go back to our way of understanding or our metaphysical assumptions wherein we garner from these in order to make way into how we conduct ourselves in our actions. In this paper then, I will explicate Bertrand