INTRODUCTION
There are many versions of phenomenology that came
after and surprisingly before Husserl mentioned it as his philosophy. Hegel
used the term phenomenology in his Phenomenology of the Spirit yet we ponder was this the phenomenology that Husserl is
stressing? Moreover, Husserls predecessors such as Kant also used the same
term. Husserl embraced phenomenology and even baptized the term much later in
his works for he was concerned first in creating arguments that are against the
trend of psychologism during his time. Psychologism was a grand perversion of
empiricism in a way that it has placed all into contingency without a way out.
Most of Husserl’s early works are devoted into giving explanations against
psychologism. “His preoccupation with refuting ‘naturalism’ and ‘psychologism’ is the dominant theme in the first volume of Logische Unterschungen.”[1]
Moreso, he wish to save the crisis that is looming especially that psychologism
is also paired with growing interest on science. Although, Husserl is for
science but towards the perversion thereof which is scienticism, he is strongly
against it, because he asserts that there is something that is objective. By
objective, he is not referring to mere possibilities with experience but
something that governs truth making as there is the truth to truths. Thus it is
his task “. . . his project of laying the groundwork of a strictly scientific
philosophy.”[2] Most celebrated are his rigorous explanations
in giving a view on what this ‘phenomenology’ is.
There were many of those who follow Husserl who
eventually broke up with him. Many claimed to be phenomenological yet the most
diehard of Husserl scholars say that his is the only phenomenology that there
is.[3]
Among those who are prominent is Jean Paul Sartre. Jean Paul Sartre gave
phenomenology an existential and psychological twist as he delved into
psychology in one of his books The Sketch
on the Theory of Emotions and later on to his magnum opus Being and Nothingness. Yet traces of
Sartre’s discord with Husserl comes from his work on Transcendence of Ego as he gives his arguments pertaining to
Husserl’s claims. The area here pertains to the ego of which is varied from
Descartes. Here then is the main concern of the paper.
SARTRE AS A PHENOMENOLOGIST
Husserl and Sartre all
look back to the influence that Descartes gave unto them of which founded the
way to their central themes pertaining to the thinking I. Descartes made that
breakthrough into giving the focus to the subject when it comes to finding out
certitude. Through methodically doubting everything, Descartes has done to a
certain extent what a radical sceptic would do, but he did not end in all out
contingency of things as he was keen on what remains to be ‘true’. Therefore,
in every moment of doubt one must secure oneself to another plain of which one
can lay rest onto.
“Now before beginning to rebuild the house
where one lives, it is not enough to knock it down, to provide building
materials and architects (or to practice
architecture oneself), and to have the plans drawn carefully, it is also
necessary to have provided oneself with another house which to live comfortably
while the rebuilding is taking place.”[4]
This tactic into the
doubting process initiated by Descartes proved that whenever one deconstructs,
he has to secure one’s self while the deconstruction takes place. Moreover,
what can be implied is that even though that this tactic could serve as a first
step into the doubting process but as it goes ad infinitum then at the end of it Descartes found that house
wherein he has to stay amidst everything deconstructed and that is the thinking
I. Needless to say, amidst the doubt, there is one thing sure of and that is
the thinking I. Coming from this vantage point, objectivity has moved from
purely objective to the evaluation of the knower, the subject. Later on, both
Husserl and Sartre would stress on the subject (given that it is the
consciousness) but Husserl followed the German obsession of objectivity coming
from transcendental aspects of consciousness which was laid out by Kant. The
German tradition focused more on what is in the mental act or the formal
structures of consciousness not of the ‘fact’ or the ‘material’. “Unlike Kant,
for instance, who approached experience from the aspect of its general validity
and necessary conditions, French philosophers from Descartes to Sartre have
been concerned mainly with questions of fact – not with the transcendental
conditions of thought, but with the actually thinking and experiencing cogito; not with the necessary but with
the sufficient conditions; not with the formal but with the ‘material’
structures of consciousness.”[5]
Although French philosophy echoes the Cartesian cogito
but Sartre added a psychological twist to it. However, what comes as a
similarity between Husserl and Sartre is the central theme of consciousness
coming from the Brentano’s intentionality. In the reduction of everything into
being grasped by consciousness, then consciousness becomes the major concern
into arriving at objectivity (Husserl) or that existential purpose (Sartre).
The concern of Sartre is not on the formal categories which are within
consciousness of which helps into arriving at objectivity for he regarded this
as an impossible take into mapping out such. He was more concerned with the
experience of consciousness of which gravitates into two poles “a) the
experience of radical autonomy from being, of freedom, a personal escape from
the threat of being or becoming a determined and derterminate ‘thing’ and b)
the recognition that consciousness has no single essence, that it cannot be
defined like other realities but only described in its polymorphous variety.”[6]
Thus, Sartre’s take on consciousness tackles on the ‘behaviour’ of
consciousness which is implied in its ability to experience.
Supposed to be consciousness should be a no-thing yet it creates its self
identification when it relates itself with objects, with beings. “Consciousness
tends to get bogged down in being. There is too
much of it. It is soft, warm, sticky, sweet, suffocating, viscous,
corpulent, flabby, expressive. We cannot comprehend it; it stands there dumb,
in bad faith.” [7]
“Consciousness alone, though embedded in being through its body, experiences
itself to be not a thing but the consciousness of things, not a being but
consciousness of being, i.e. a no-thing,
separated from being by nothing but itself.”[8]
Thus coming from the fact that it mistakenly relates itself as a being within
the multitude of beings, then acknowledging that the identification of
consciousness with being can be changed presupposes that consciousness indeed
is a no thing i.e. a blank canvass wherein man can paint more or undo. This is
where freedom lies, when one acknowledges that no-thing structure of one’s
consciousness and thus one is ‘free’ to associate, accumulate meaning along the
way.
The notion of intentionality echoes on Sartre as
consciousness indeed is always conscious of an object i.e. being.
Intentionality is transcendence as consciousness is oriented towards something
which is not itself. This is where true freedom is at, the ability to change to
a something beyond itself.
Sartre stressed on consciousness in the real as opposed
to Husserl as a substrate of where the fundamental categories are at. Real in
the sense that it is always related to the experience of individuals and not
the kind of phenomenology that is obsessed with hardcore objectivity but with
something practical and that is existential. Moreover, let us go to the points
where Sartre drafted his own brand of phenomenology as he stems away from
Husserl.
TRANSCENDENCE
OF THE EGO?
“The phenomenology of Husserl was a reflexive
inquiry, or a philosophy of consciousness.” [9]
Husserl’s main objective again is to map out the structures of consciousness in order to bridge the link between the subject and the object into gaining certitude. Husserl has first dedicated a testament onto objectivity by tackling the objects themselves and then in his later works focus on the subject of which is the recipient of the world. That is why, eventually Husserl was not anymore concerned on the experience of consciousness but more on to what is within consciousness that gives ‘certitude’ to the objects perceived. Moreover, consciousness for Husserl “is consciousness of an object and composes no part of the object.”[10] The consciousness is in-itself independent from the object and coming from this assertion, he is hinting on the fact that consciousness is can be a totally separate entity, thus he recourse to the notion of an ego which has all the constructs in order to 'take on' objects. The germs of such ideas can be read in his Logical Investigations Vol I where he hints of a unifying principle of all areas of the sciences. In the chapter The Idea of Pure Logic the main question he raised is “what makes science a science?”
Husserl’s main objective again is to map out the structures of consciousness in order to bridge the link between the subject and the object into gaining certitude. Husserl has first dedicated a testament onto objectivity by tackling the objects themselves and then in his later works focus on the subject of which is the recipient of the world. That is why, eventually Husserl was not anymore concerned on the experience of consciousness but more on to what is within consciousness that gives ‘certitude’ to the objects perceived. Moreover, consciousness for Husserl “is consciousness of an object and composes no part of the object.”[10] The consciousness is in-itself independent from the object and coming from this assertion, he is hinting on the fact that consciousness is can be a totally separate entity, thus he recourse to the notion of an ego which has all the constructs in order to 'take on' objects. The germs of such ideas can be read in his Logical Investigations Vol I where he hints of a unifying principle of all areas of the sciences. In the chapter The Idea of Pure Logic the main question he raised is “what makes science a science?”
“Science is ,
in the first place a unified item in anthropology: it is a unity of acts of
thinking, of thought-dispositions, as well as of certain external arrangements
pertinent thereto. . . . We are rather interested in what makes science
science.” [11]
Although this section
concerns with Husserl want to establish about an overarching theory of science
which can be seen as not yet concerning the structures of consciousness, but it
is evidential enough that along the way he mentions of interconnections of all
sciences, of all truths and together with their validity of which may pertain
to the functional aspect of consciousness through logic, which may hint of the
externality of consciousness as a logical entity but also the logic behind the
logic which consciousness permeates itself through specific scientific
disciplines. “All scientific procedures of the objective sciences of fact are
governed, as Descartes and Leibniz saw, not by psychological contingency, but
by an ideal norm.”[12]
Looking at Husserl’s phenomenology gives us a notion of
it being dry and devoid of a kind of ‘immediate experience’ that Sartre would
stress upon. Not only is Husserl concerned with inner structures of
consciousness that can help us in the quest of validating objectivity but he even
extends to the point of objectivity in letting objects as such in an ‘idealistic’ fashion. “Husserl insisted
that the phenomenologist ‘bracket’ questions of fact.”[13]
This has become also an epistemic concern as the “theory of knowledge need not
to be closeted with the activities of consciousness, but could go directly in
reflection to the intended objects of consciousness and the principles
governing them.”[14]
Eventually, there is this implication of an ego that
governs intentionality of which possesses the above mentioned structures.
However, the Sartre contends if ever this ego is indeed a substrate or an
object. “Is the I that we encounter in our consciousness made possible by the
synthetic unity of our representations, or is it the I which in fact unites the
representations to each other?”[15]
The question aims to attack how the followers of Kant viewed ego of which
Husserl too claims especially on the hinting of the inevitability of an ego to
be a reflection of the ‘I think’, more or like a ‘me’. “It is a real
consciousness accessible to each of us soon as the ‘reduction’ is performed.
And it is indeed this transcendental consciousness which constitutes our
empirical consciousness, our consciousness in
the world, our consciousness with its psychic and psychophysical me.[16]
“But we raise the following question: is not this psychic and psycho-physical me enough? Need one double it with a
transcendental I, a structure of
absolute consciousness?” [17] To Sartre there is no more need to
recourse to the 'unifying and individualizing I’ because consciousness as being
conscious of something always transcends itself into the relation with objects.
Thus there can be no I without an object. I is always in relation to the
object, but this cannot be an I for an I is a product of refletion. There can
be no transcendental ego that is absolute and an isolate. Consciousness finds
itself in attachment to being, to others. "It unifies itself by escaping
itself."[18]
Moreover, Husserl justifies that
this so called I can be proven via an examination on memory wherein one recalls
the I. While reflecting on consciousness via memory, we can see the I. Sartre
replies that “. . . but the I was no inhabiting this consciousness. It was only
consciousness of the object and non-positional consciousness of itself. . .
there was no I in the unreflected consciousness.”[19]
Upon memory, what we can recall is consciousness being conscious not that of an
I. In memory, it is the unreflected consciousness that we gain insight to, for
‘it’ was immersed in intentionality not reflection.
CONSCIOUSNESS FOR EXISTENTIALISM
Sartre’s
project into criticizing Husserl was that of revealing that there can be no
transcendent ego as mentioned above. But to devote oneself into finding that
ego deviates us from what really matters. Although finding that domain of the
purest of logic and to be able to have a description of it ‘may’ solve once and
for all the question concerning truths and objectivity, but the impossibility
presented to attain such calls us to redirect our ‘conscious’ efforts towards
something else. Even via memory, the I cannot be attained, thus there can be no
instance that consciousness is ‘removed’ from the world because it is always
conscious of the world, on facts. Thus the focus is on being, is on the world
and even the nausea of consciousness of self-identification to beings which is
not it. The shift now points towards into the scenario wherein what are we to
consider urgent because what we have is that indeed we are immersed in the
world and later on it is called in existentialist language ‘facticity’. This
then were Sartre deviates from Husserl as matters of fact are present and
demands ‘care’ into how we relate to it. The concern is not anymore how Husserl
would save science, but on how we could relate to the world in order to live.
Thus, the drive is bring consciousness to the core of it always conscious of
something and ought to relate with it, to live and not to find its absolute
erasure by finding that transcendent ego, the I in consciousness.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Descartes, Rene. Discourse on Method and Related Writings translated by Desmond
Clarke. New York: Penguin Books.
1999.
Husserl, Edmund. Logical Investigations Vol I
translated by J.N. Findlay. New York: Routledge. 2001.
_________. Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy: Philosophy as Rigorous
Science and Philosophy and the Crisis of
the European Man translated by Quentin Lauer. New York: Harper and Row Publisher. 1965.
Lee, E. & Mandelbaum, M. Phenomenology and Existentialism.
Baltimore: The John Hopkins Press.
1967.
Sartre, Jean Paul. The Transcendence of the Ego translated by Forrest Williams and
Robert Kirkpatrick. New York: Hill and
Wang . 1960.
[1] Husserl, Edmund. Phenomenology
and the Crisis of Philosophy: Philosophy as Rigorous Science and Philosophy and
the Crisis of the European Man translated by Quentin Lauer. New York: Harper
and Row Publisher. 1965. p. 3.
[2] Ibid. p. 4
[3] According to a footnote on the translation by Quentine Lauer on the
introduction to the Phenomenology and the
Crisis of Philosophy: Philosophy as Rigorous Science and Philosophy and the
Crisis of the European Man he says that “many of Husserl’s most ardent
disciples are preferred to base their own investigations on the earlier
‘practical’ method than on the later idealistic theory. . .”. Thus, this is
where the divide happens; however, if they were to adopt the earlier Husserl
and the reject the later one, it does not mean a total overhaul of the thoughts
of the man because the later is implied in this earlier works.
[4] Descartes, Rene. Discourse on
Method and Related Writings translated by Desmond Clarke. New York: Penguin
Books. 1999. pp. 18-19.
[5] Lee, E. & Mandelbaum, M. Phenomenology
and Existentialism. Baltimore: The John Hopkins Press. 1967. P.142. (The
section is the sixth essay in the book entitled as Sartre as Phenomenologist and as Existential Psychoanalyst by James
M. Edie.)
[6] Ibid. p.143.
[7] Ibid. p.145.
[8] Ibid. p.145.
[9] Sartre, Jean Paul. The
Transcendence of the Ego translated by Forrest Williams and Robert
Kirkpatrick. New York: Hill and Wang . 1960. p. 12.
[10] Ibid. p.13.
[11] Husserl, Edmund. Logical
Investigations Vol I translated
by J.N. Findlay. New York: Routledge. 2001. p.144
[12] Ibid. p. 161.
[13] Sartre, Jean Paul. The
Transcendence of the Ego translated by Forrest Williams and Robert
Kirkpatrick. New York: Hill and Wang . 1960. p. 16.
[14] Ibid. p.15.
[15] Ibid. p.34.
[16] Ibid. pp.35-36.
[17] Ibid. p.36.
[18] Ibid. p. 38.
[19] Ibid. p.47.
Comments
Post a Comment